Philo Papers

An Alternative Paradigm for Human Solidarity: A Levinasian Perspective

Introduction
This paper is an attempt to suggest an alternative view from a philosophical standpoint that could serve as a possible paradigm for human solidarity. But before delving on this topic, this paper will first present the fundamentality of solidarity in human existence. Then this fundamentality will be explained in terms of the social dimension of our existence. Afterwards, it will evaluate the paradigm behind the limited way for solidarity, which seems to defeat the purpose of solidarity. After the exposition of the inadequacy of such paradigm, this paper will explore the thoughts of Emmanuel Levinas whose advocacy to be responsible for others is seen as a significant idea in an attempt to find for a philosophical alternative view that could possibly be effective for human solidarity. In particular, this paper will focus on Levinas’s two basic concepts: The Other whose infinity contained in the face names the Other’s incomprehensible character which is the stepping stone in the idea of responsibility; and the Third Party as a threshold for all others where solidarity among all others will be established. This paper will end by presenting the implication of Levinas’ thoughts in view of their relevance to present the paradigm for human solidarity.
Part I:  Human Solidarity and Its Problem
Solidarity as Fundamental in Human Existence[1]
Human existence begins and ends with solidarity. Our individual birth for instance is not a solitary event that merely marks the history of our personal life, but also in the lives of many others, especially those immediate to us such as our family. Because of our birth, they are moved into one in their desire for a successful delivery and in their experience of thrill and joy to see our presence. It would mean then that new relationship emanating from this new life is added to their lives. Our birth affects them in terms of bringing to them a spring of hope and inspiration to live a fuller way of life.
Although this solidarity that is there in our birth appears vividly in our family, this solidarity in birth is there even beyond this limited circle. It is an integral part of our human experience that we take joy in the appearance of a new baby. Even when the child is not related to us, its presence somehow gives us a lovingness of joy. We sense that this baby, be it Asian, American, African or European, is a new addition to our human family. Our lives have been amplified when this child is born. If this child, for instance, is hungry, we have a vague sense or inner feeling of obligation that we should provide food for him or her. This marks that beyond relatedness every human baby is in some way part of our lives.
Death, on the other hand, also possesses an element where human solidarity is experienced. We may perceive death as an event for an individual alone, a totally individual experience. Heidegger, for instance, in Being and Time, will consider death as something which an individual experiences in a completely individual way. The idea is: I die as an individual and no one else dies with me. In opposition to Heidegger’s position is the human experience that death is not completely solitary. In our dying moment, we acknowledge in us our desire for our immediate family members to be there with us, to be together wherein, ideally, we bid farewell to them and them to us. It is in this togetherness that a sense of solidarity is manifested.   
Our death has a profound significance which transcends even outside the circle of our immediate family and friends. It calls for our awareness that our community and the entire humanity will henceforth be lacking something. Our death affects them for our presence makes a difference in some time.  When we die our contributions to their lives will have their end thus creating a vacuum to their lives. Although our loss may not be printed in a modern newspaper, we know for a fact that it will be a significant loss. At times when there is a feeling of emptiness within because of a loss of someone, we find ourselves filled in the presence of our family members and in the sympathy of others. Even in funerals and burials, we like to pay homage to express our being one in the moment of pain and sorrow. (I think of the death of the late President Corazon Aquino.) In the case of death, we realize the value of togetherness. Hence, our deaths reveal our oneness with other people.
These phenomena (our birth and our death) mark the significance of solidarity in our lives. It is given. It’s always with us. However, making such a claim leaves no questions. What makes solidarity fundamental in our human existence?  What could be the possible root to explain this fundamentality?  Why are we capable for solidarity?
From this point, I would like to explain the fundamentality of solidarity from the social dimension of our human existence. We may be unique different individuals separate from one another but we are also individuals who are also with others, through others and for others. John Donne says “no man is an island”. We cannot deny that we need others and they need us.
Solidarity and Sociality[2]
Every aspect of our human existence is social. The others are always presupposed in any individual activities. We live with other human beings. My study for example makes sense because they are also taken up by other persons. I deal with my teachers, my classmates, and my fellow students in school. This is usually what a student does. In this case, I am inevitably in contact with other people. Even in the activities that I perform alone such as studying individually is social in character. I may not perform them with others but I learn to do it from others, I do it through others and for others.[3] My ability to read and write, for instance, is because of my parents at home and teachers in school who taught me since childhood. Hence, reading and writing have their marks of influence in my parents and teachers. Moreover, the pencil or pen, papers and books that I use in my studying are products of other people. Through them, I could possibly use materials for my study. Also, the fact that I am able to study signifies the presence of others especially my parents whose support, either financially or morally, is constant. Through them, my study in some way is made possible. In addition, my study is also not merely driven by my selfish motives. I study that I may help maybe to my immediate family members first and then to others in the future. Hence, I study for others although I study alone.  
In his article, The Social Dimensions of Human Existence, Manuel Dy Jr. further explains that even in our desire just to be alone is social for the reason that this desire might be the effect of other’s pressures, or because we would like to improve our relationship with others through our solitary reflection or because maybe we would like to give an impression for being independent from others.[4]  
Hence, given that human existence is social in everything; solidarity is always possible. When we choose to be in solidarity, it would possibly come into the view. Our sociality thus brings us into the zone of solidarity.  Because of this, solidarity has its place of significance to bring it into discussion. However, what is human solidarity? How do we define it?   
Solidarity in “Sameness” as its Primary Basis and its Problem
            Human solidarity is defined in various forms. Dictionary defines solidarity as “unity of interests, sympathies, etc., as among members of the same class”[5] Human solidarity, moreover, is understood also as “founded on mutual respect of each other’s uniqueness and a deep sense of appreciation of our common humanity”[6] Lastly, human solidarity is “conceived as a reciprocal practice”.[7] Cohesiveness is achieved in a symmetrical relationship.   
 Different as they may appear, the definitions given above have in common in their basis for solidarity i.e. according to “sameness”. The first definition implies that solidarity would come into the picture when everyone manifests a common interests and sympathies. We gather for the same cause, the same purpose, the same goal etc. Notice that there is an idea of commonality of interests or sympathies which leads to unity. This commonality could better be identified as bottom line where the “sameness” lies, making the unity possible. In this case, there could never be unity when there is no oneness and there could never be oneness without having things in common. In other words, unity comes when there is a sense of likeness. Expounding the second and the third definitions, solidarity is established when everyone manifests the same attitudes or
goals or interests or understandings to everyone. We must do the same thing to others according to what they have done to us. When we received respect, respect must also be given. In this regard, what drives human to solidarity is the idea of ‘the same”. Hence, sameness is what holds humans together to have a sense of solidarity. Although there could be differences but ultimately solidarity rests on a certain kind of sameness or “things in common”. From this vantage point, I would like to deal with the idea of solidarity as a form of togetherness (organization, groups, association etc) driven by essential reason where its primary basis is the idea of commonality or “sameness”.  
            This conception of human solidarity can be traced back to the Greek philosophical tradition, especially found in Aristotle’s model of friendship. In returning to Aristotle’s form of friendship we find an emphasis on sameness as source of bond.[8] This account of friendship, as objective-centered, seeks some objective qualities—specific values, virtues or understanding—of a friend to explain a friendly bond.[9] The common values or understanding of friends ensure that they will share affective and rational apprehensions of any ethical situations. This commonality of virtues is clearly specified in some elements of Aristotle’s account of prefect friendship.[10]
            First, one loves a true friend for his own sake. All forms of friendship require love of the friend for his own sake; only in perfect friendship, however, does this translate into love of the other for what he essentially is, since virtue is central to a good man’s character. True friendship thus is defined by the sameness of friends in their virtue; good men are attracted to one another in friendship because ‘like is dear to like’.[11]
            Second and lastly, true friend is another self. Perfect friendship involves making our friend’s fortunes your own: he becomes another self; his pleasure and pains known as if they were yours. So Aristotle repeatedly suggests that true friends share ‘a single soul’ and that a true friend is ‘a second self.’ The expansion of the boundaries of concern to include a friend is helped along by the likeness of desires and aversions implied by habituation into shared excellence.[12]
            Using Aristotle’s objective account of friendship leads us to his notion of civic solidarity, where the common features of character is the basis of drawing us together. Everyone must relate on the basis of shared understanding. A successful statesman for instance must cultivate in himself like-mindedness among citizens about the definitions of virtue and justice in a state.[13] For Aristotle then, the bonds between citizens are unequivocally premised on sameness, providing the basis for stable solidarity.[14]
            Because Aristotle sees bond on the plane of sameness, he treats differences as detracting from the relationship. For Aristotle, difference is a sign of deficiency in a friendship. On Aristotle’s account, if my friend and I differ in anything relating to the ethical life, this is either a call for me to bring myself into line or sign that my friend may not be my equal in virtue (which would immediately threaten our friendship). There can of course be differences between perfect friends: while Aristotle sees the ethical domain as expansive, the life of circumstances of virtuous men will differ, and such men may hold differentiated social roles (from among the following the full development of virtues). Yet to the extent that a canonically defined human good leaves room for some differences in the affects and life plans of virtuous men, attentiveness to such differences is not thought by Aristotle to be constitutive of true friendship. Where such differences cannot be ignored as non-ethical, they imperil a friendship.[15]
            Thereof, I would like to affirm a sort of influence from Aristotle in the definition of solidarity enumerated above. Aristotle’s theory of friendship, either personal or civic, is clearly identifiable in one of our concepts of solidarity. Both have come to use sameness as ground of coming together or friendship. Although the ideas of solidarity presented take in different forms and different ways but ultimately they rest on a certain commonality. So sameness becomes the primary foundation for solidarity.
            The thought of Aristotle is indeed a good starting point for solidarity but its inadequacy lies when it does not also attend to differences.  This conception would only yield a kind of violence and division.  In our present condition, there are somehow marks of influences of such conception of solidarity (based on sameness) which leaves some marks of social problems in our society.   
            One social problem brought about by the idea of sameness is the “frat” violence. Despite, as we may say, the high ideals of fraternities, acts of violence and hostilities inevitably overshadow such ideals. Undeniably, there are events of violent confrontation between rival fraternities causing injuries to every member.  The common act of violence is generally called as “rumble”. Everyone in a fraternity clashes against the other members of a rival fraternity. This event is not new to us especially those who happen to have in contact with members of many different fraternities.  And still this violence exists among fraternities. Fraternity, in this sense, becomes nothing more than the dangerous prattle of the spoiled, attention-hungry boy whose self-worth is defined by the capacity to inflict pain, destruction and even death on others.[16]
            In this event, one could question the reason behind this violence. In my own perspective, I see that hostility among some members of rival fraternities is the failure to respect the difference of every fraternity. The tendency to limit brotherhood or sisterhood only to those who belong to same fraternity could be the possible reason for such violence. Because of such conception, one is ready to inflict pain to other members of different fraternities or one is ready to fight for the brotherhood of the same fraternity. The others who have different fraternities are seen as threats or enemies simply because they belong to a different fraternity. Brotherhood or sisterhood, in this case, turns to have exclusivity. As a result, solidarity in terms of having things in common sometimes could yield violence and division. (Although there could be more concrete situations that manifest such a problem, I chose this as the subject of my problem as stepping stone to consider the wider perspective.)
If solidarity would ultimately rests on the idea of commonality such as what is presented above, then it could be better to search for an alternative view that sustains solidarity despite differences. We can no longer absolutely rely on the paradigm of solidarity founded on the idea of “sameness” for, as we see, it reveals to us its flawed assumptions. We have to explore on other horizon that can accommodate for our search. And if we are to look closely, there is no need to trace back as far as ancient philosophical traditions for this search. Emmanuel Levinas, one of the widely respected thinkers of our century provides us a worldview that could serve as a possible paradigm for human solidarity.
Part II: Emmanuel Levinas on The Other, and The Third Party
The Other and the Call to Responsibility
The first truth that I find myself before the Other is that the Other reveals herself as Other, separate and different from me. Although there is a clear essential identity as human being that resembles the Other and me, which Levinas does not deny, it does not, however, reduce the radical alterity the Other presents.[17]  And by being other offers me no place in grasping her within the horizon of being in general and in possessing her. Levinas says “that which escapes comprehension in the other (autrui) is her” as other.[18]
Levinas uses the idea of infinity to represent the irreducibility of the Other. This so-called infinity is contained and unraveled in the Other’s face.[19] However, in what way does this infinity reveal in the face? What does Levinas mean by the “face”?  Levinas does not merely mean the literal perception of the face consisting of the eyes, forehead, ears, lips, etc. but rather in the manner the Other presents herself as other i.e. irreducible and transcendent. In a conversation with Philippe Nemo, Levinas remarks that “the relation with the face can surely be dominated by perception, but what is specifically the face is cannot be reduced to that.”[20] The face itself, in its exposure, has an element of uprightness because it takes no defense. In its exposure, I can do anything to it because it is which that stays most naked and most destitute. But it is also which forbids me to do against it. Levinas, to attests this poverty, cites our putting on poses and taking on countenance on our face. Moreover, the face is signification without context. For its signification, in a usual sense of the term, is not relative to a particular context. In other words, the meaning of the face is not in its relation to another thing. We cannot just simply identify the face for example by its being a son of affluent family, or in the manner of presenting herself, or in the way of behaving, or in physical features, etc.  “The face is meaning all by itself. You are you.”[21] In this description of the face, one can say that the face is not merely an appearance of itself but rather it is what eludes the embrace of my categorical thought.[22]  This further suggests that to look at the face is to look at the Other’s radical alterity.[23]      
To clarify further, Levinas employs the term ‘epiphany’. Levinas associates “epiphany” with the “manifestation” of the Other’s otherness. The appearance of the Other is characterized not just by “being there”. By “being there” entails the allowing of the ego to comprehend the Other in the horizon of being in general. But in the face-to-face encounter with the Other, I am not facing a thing that I can perceive and reduce to either an object of my enjoyment or to my egoistic concepts through my grasping hand and intellect.[24] This event unravels the Other’s refusal to be contained and to be comprehended against the “totalizing system”[25].  Thereof, the Other, by its appearance, commands a response different from knowledge. Although inevitably I have knowledge of the Other’s manifestation and the demands put on me, but the epiphany needs a response beyond my pretheoretical perspective. Hence by the Other’s simply appearance, she also gives commands.
But how can I give assurance that the command coming from the Other will not appear as something authoritative, and does not lead to a form of violence, maybe because of my egoistic reaction? How can the Other commands me without oppressing me? In other words, how can this opposition and demand of the Other be situated in an ethical form?[26]  
The command is ethical for it calls for duty not in the form of compelling, bribery, or manipulation.[27] Despite the supremacy of the Other he does not try to take control over me the way my egoism does but rather in his poverty. In the words of Levinas:
The first word of the face is the “Thou shall not kill.” It is an order. There is a commandment in the appearance of the face, as if a master spoke to me. However, at the same time, the face of the Other is destitute; it is the poor for whom I can do all and to whom I owe all. And me, whoever I may be, but as a “first person,” I am he who finds the resources to respond to the call.”[28]

Thereof, Levinas tells us that the other challenges me through his destitution. He challenges me from his height and from his humility as well.[29] What makes the command ethical is the virtue of her destitution because she neither imposes her will on me nor subjugate my freedom but rather, commands my generosity and compassion.[30] In this event, the command works as a form of an invitation and a welcome from her that moves me to draw myself near her and to do my responsibility for her as my neighbor without my being commanded nor forced by her or anything.  If I recognize the command, it shatters my egoism and breaks myself away from self-preoccupation. This is because in acknowledging such a command I also simultaneously move toward the other to respond, to become responsible. Having said yes to this command is a kind of transcendence and a realization of my own humanity because I permit myself to an ethical relation with the other.[31]  Thus the command through the epiphany of the face reveals the ethical dimension of my humanity.  
When the Other appeals to me, the humble plea does not merely appeal to my goodness but particularly to my responsibility.  The ultimate command is responsibility. Responsibility here is of course understood as responsibility for the Other not just responsibility for my own deed. It transcends the field of my egoism toward what does not matter to me.[32] This responsibility is concretely expressed by doing good for the Other and giving oneself for the service of the Other without waiting for reciprocity. The Other’s responsibility in my regard is her affair. In this case, I must have a generous orientation toward the Other even if the Other does not assume her responsibility on me. 
Speaking further, Levinas considered responsibility as my fundamental structure. This goes to follow that responsibility precedes my freedom. Levinas says that “I am responsible for him without even having taken on responsibilities in his regard; his responsibility is incumbent on me.[33] In this sense it could “be considered a priori”.[34] It is there without my choosing it. Accordingly, this makes my capability to be responsible possible.  Moreover, it also makes it clear that my “unicity” with the other is in a completely different way. The tie between me and the Other is not under comprehension or perception which goes towards adequation but as a matter of responsibility. In a conversation with Philippe Nemo, Levinas says:
The tie with the Other is knotted only as responsibility, this moreover, whether accepted or refused, whether knowing or not knowing how to assume it, whether able to or unable to do something concrete for the Other. To give. To be human spirit, that’s it.[35]

Moreover, the above statement also reveals an idea of a fundamental option. The face turns directly toward me and me alone—face-a-face. I must answer. And “how I answer depends on my freedom. I must say “yes” but I can say “no”.”[36] Hence, although part of me is being responsible for others, it does not ultimately discard my freedom. But if I commit myself positively to be responsible for the other, this responsibility would bring me to fraternal close to her in a bond of solidarity. I would then make myself available and declare: “me voice—“Here I am”.”[37]
Sociality and the Third Party
Notice that in the previous discussion, I seem to present merely a relation involving of two persons, the Other and the I. I discuss that the manifestation of the Other calls for a welcoming response the face signifies. Obedience to this demand reveals that I use my freedom to take responsibility for the Other. But what about my relation to another Other who is beside and behind the immediate Other? Is my relation consists only of a single Other?
Levinas does not ignore the presence of the other Other. The You appearing in the epiphany of the face is not particular and privatized, but universal. The Other does not seek clandestine intimacy but places itself in the full light of revelation. Language could testify that being able to speak, for instance, reveals the fact that the other and the I belong to a certain language community. It is something that is actually shared with. In the epiphany of the Other, the third also looks at me.[38] Levinas says:
Language as the presence of the face, does not invite complicity with the preferred being, the self-sufficient ‘I-Thou’ forgetful of the universe; in its frankness it refuses the clandestinity….The third party also looks at me in the eyes of the other….[39]

When I meet the naked face of this one Other, I am also with all others, who call to me just humbly and with just as much imperative as does this one Other standing before me.[40] As Levinas puts it:
The epiphany of the face opens up humanity….the presence of the face, the infinity of the Other, is a destituteness, a presence of the third (that is, of the whole of humanity which looks at us)….[41]

It is for this reason that Levinas considered the I-Other relation as “social relation” or simply as sociality. The otherness of the other has an essentially social extension: his alterity contains an immediate reference to all others. Therefore, the third seems to be the name for the Other inasmuch as the Other is multiple and anonymous but always having a face and speech.[42]
It seems then that our “universal” kinship does not derive from some common quality or qualities but of an ethical structure or character. As our usual basis of identification, race for instance refers everything to “likeness” or “sameness”—to one’s own race, one’s own people, and one’s own blood—so that the ‘others’, those who do not belong to my race, people, or blood, are excluded all the way if necessary, to the point of denial or even annihilation (holocaust). To the contrary, a truly humane kinship includes all others precisely on the basis of their otherness and difference, as expressed in the face.[43]
Implication on Human Solidarity
            Human solidarity, in its tendency to take “sameness” as its primary basis, has proven itself to be inadequate and limited.  What has resulted from this viewpoint is a kind of “categorical” solidarity. We see it in the example given above. Different groups of organizations of people bringing the spirit of solidarity with their own unified visions come into the picture. However, they do not just emerge but incite divisions and violence.  
Emmanuel Levinas, in his own philosophy, take another paradigm for human solidarity. In the above discussion, he has clearly opposed the kind of relation with the Other in terms of comprehension which reduce the Other into the horizon of The Same. Speaking of this, my dealing with the Other must not be basically according to sameness.  Levinas suggests that my relation with the Other is irreducible to this kind of apprehension. Consequently, for Levinas, solidarity is not primarily caused for having the same purpose, interests, and goals. Because of this, we could see Levinas’ opposition to Aristotle’s model of friendship. Aristotle advocates commonality as the basis for friendship and even in the civic friendship.  And we see that sameness is rooted in objectivity. Unlike Aristotle’s model of friendship, Levinas upholds the otherness of the Other. The alterity of the Other contained in the face reveals to me her difference and at the same time opens up an idea of infinity which signifies the irreducibility of the Other. What eludes in my comprehension is the otherness of the other. With this, the Other gives her refusal to be contained in a totalizing system. This refusal simultaneously poses a command for me. The command, as we see, is a call for responsibility to the Other. Hence, from the otherness of the Other emanates responsibility. And when I response to this call, it is a responsibility that binds the Other and the me.   
            Speaking broadly, Levinas’ idea about the ethical relationship with the Other has its significance to my relationship to all Others and establish a new structure of solidarity. In his book, Totality and Infinity, he calls it (all others) as the third party which is basically referred to the “whole of humanity”[44]. The manifestation of the third is seen in the epiphany of the Other’s face. The face of the Other, as it manifests, attests the presence of the third because the epiphany of the face qua face opens humanity. And since all Others, independent of whether I have met them or not, have faces, they look at me for the same reason with the Other whose face and words reach me here and now. Although I cannot get to know everyone, this does not exempt my response for them the I must response to the Other. They appeal to my devotion like the Other. Given such an exposition, this will entail that my response is not merely confined to the immediate Other but also extended to the other Others which basically termed as “the third”.   Hence, Levinas clearly opt for responsibility for the Other as the basis for a humane society. Levinas says:
           That all men are brothers is not explained by resemblance, nor by a common cause….It is responsibility before a face looking at me as absolutely foreign (and the epiphany of the face coincides with these two moments) that constitutes the original fact of fraternity.[45]
           
Thus, it is not “sameness” that binds us in drawing us together but responsibility. The comprehension driven by an idea of “things in common” is not an appropriate measure in solidarity. The point is that despite any differences in the level of understandings or advocacies I could still be in solidarity with other people. In view of such situation, what drives me to do as such is responsibility.
With all this, I believe that the concept of Levinas particularly being responsible for all others would pave the way to a better sense of human solidarity. This is because being together with others does not come first by comprehension but by being responsible for others even to the strangers I meet along the way.  
Conclusion
Maintaining the claim that human solidarity is always part of our human existence, it becomes a subject that must not be taken for granted. As social being, we can neither escape ourselves in meeting other people where an avenue of solidarity is just within reach. However, the prevailing conception of solidarity as influenced by Aristotle has limited itself by taking commonality as its primary basis. In effect of such paradigm is the emergence of “categorized” solidarities which in some way have failed to serve their purpose for they only provoke division and violence. Such an inadequacy has led this paper to affirm Emmanuel Levinas’ thought as an alternative view that concerns for a better sense of solidarity. For Levinas, it is not the “sameness” but the otherness of the Other that must be the binding factor of solidarity. This is because in my ethical relation with the Other, the Other’s otherness demands a different response not in a form of comprehension of sameness but responsibility. In such a manner, there is a hope that a stronger sense of solidarity would established in applying the philosophy of Levinas for “responsibility tolerates no delays”.[46]
In presenting the Levinas’ philosophical exposition of the ethical relation with the Other and all Others, I do not intend to propose a revolutionary shift of viewpoint as if it were the only possible paradigm in search for solidarity. This presentation of the alternative paradigm works as a form of invitation to reflect our own sense of solidarity. Like Emmanuel Levinas’ the Other, the content of this paper does not impose its will nor subjugate your freedom but commands your generosity.  



BIBLIOGRAPHY
Works by Emmanuel Levinas
Books

Levinas, Emmanuel.  Alterity and Transcendence. Translated by Michael B. Smith. New Yrok: Columbia University Press, 1999.

________________. Basic Philosophical Writings. Edited by Adrian T. Peperzak, Simon Critchley, and Robert Bernasconi. Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1996.

________________. Ethics and Infinity. Conversation with Philippe Nemo. Translated by Richard Cohen. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1985.

________________. Totality and Infinity. An Essay on Exteriority. Transalated by by Alphonso Lingis. Pennsylvania: Duquesne University Press, 1969.


Works on the Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas
Books
Burggraeve, Roger. The Wisdom of Love in the Service of Love: Emmanuel Levinas on Justice, Peace and Human Rights. Translated by Jeffrey Bloechl. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. 2002.

Peperzak, Adrian T. Beyond: The Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas. Illinois Northwestern University Press. 1997.

Unpublished Materials

Capili, April. “Levinas on Creation, Subjectivity and Responsibility”,(2008). 1-7.

Araneta Marlone. “Emmanuel Levinas’s Being-Responsible for Others as an Ethical Basis for Peace in Mindanao.” Masters Thesis, Ateneo De Manila University, 2006.  


Works on Human Solidarity
Books

Dy Jr., Manuel. Contemporary Social Philosophy, Quezon City: JMC Press, 1994.  

Unpublished Article

Moga, Micheal Fr. “Human Solidarity”. 1-10.   


Online Sources

Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged, (HarperCollins Publishers 1991, 1994, 1998, 2000, 2003); available from http://www.thefreedictionary.com/solidarity; Internet.  Accessed 01 February 2011.

Lourdes Quisumbing, “Values Education for Human Solidarity,” available from http://www.humiliationstudies.org/documents/QuisumbingSolidarity.pdf; Internet. Accessed 08 February 2011.

Micheal Hoelzl, “Recognizing the Sacrificial Victim: The Problem of Solidarity for Critical Social Theory,” Journal for Cultural and Religious Theory vol. 6 no. 1 (December 2004): [journal-online] 45-64. PURL: http://www.jcrt.org/archives/06.1/hoelzl.pdf;  Internet. Accessed 21 January 2011.

David Kahane, “Diversity, Solidarity and Civic Friendship,” Journal of Political Philosophy (1999) [journal on-line]; available from http://www.uofaweb.ualberta.ca/philosophy/pdfs/kahane_solidarity.pdf; Internet; accessed 01 March 2011.



[1] I am indebted in this part to Fr. Michael Moga, “Human Solidarity”, 1-9.
[2] I am indebted in this part to Manuel Dy, “The Social Dimensions of Human Existence,” Contemporary Social Philosophy, (Quezon City: JMC Press, 1994).  1-7.
[3] Manuel Dy, “The Social Dimensions of Human Existence,” 3.

[4] Ibid., 3.
                [5] Collins English Dictionary – Complete and Unabridged, (HarperCollins Publishers 1991, 1994, 1998, 2000, 2003); available from http://www.thefreedictionary.com/solidarity; Internet.  Accessed 01 February 2011.
                [6] Lourdes Quisumbing, “Values Education for Human Solidarity,” available from http://www.humiliationstudies.org/documents/QuisumbingSolidarity.pdf; Internet. Accessed 08 February 2011, 1.
                [7] Micheal Hoelzl, “Recognizing the Sacrificial Victim: The Problem of Solidarity for Critical Social Theory,” Journal for Cultural and Religious Theory vol. 6 no. 1 (December 2004): 45-64. PURL: http://www.jcrt.org/archives/06.1/hoelzl.pdf;  Internet. Accessed 21 January 2011. 46.
[8] Kahane, “Diversity, Solidarity and Civic Friendship,” Journal of Political Philosophy (1999) [journal on-line]; available from http://www.uofaweb.ualberta.ca/philosophy/pdfs/kahane_solidarity.pdf; Internet; accessed 01 March 2011.  2.
[9] Ibid., 3.
[10] Ibid., 5.
[11] Kahane, “Diversity, Solidarity and Civic Friendship,” 5.
[12] Ibid., 5. 
[13] Ibid., 6.
[14] Ibid., 7.
[15] Kahane, “Diversity, Solidarity and Civic Friendship,” 6.  
[16] Available from: http://newsinfo.inquirer.net/breakingnews/nation/view/20070905-86932/Frat_elders_responsible_for_cycle_of_violence%2C_says_Reyes
[17] Peperzak, Beyond: The Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas (Illinois: Northwestern Press, 1997), 124.  
[18] Levinas, “Transcendence and Height,” Basic Philosophical Writings, ed. Adrian Peperzak, et al, (New York: Indiana University Press, 1996),  9.
[19]  Araneta Marlone. “Emmanuel Levinas’s Being-Responsible for Others as an Ethical
Basis for Peace in Mindanao.” Masters Thesis, (Ateneo De Manila University, 2006), 100.
[20]  Levinas,  Ethics and Infinity: Conversation with Philippe Nemo, translated by Richard Cohen. (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1985), 85-86. 

[21] Ibid., 85-86.
[22]  Levinas,  Ethics and Infinity: Conversation with Philippe Nemo, 86-87.
[23] Araneta, 103.  

[24] April Capili, Levinas on Creation, Subjectivity and Responsibility, 2. 
[25] The Other is approached not in correspondence to her otherness but within the horizon of comprehension. The understanding of the Other consists in going beyond the particularity of the Other and placing the Other into horizon perceiving upon the knowledge of universal. Cited from: Levinas, “Is Ontology Fundamental?,” Basic Philosophical Writings, ed. Adrian Peperzak, et al, (New York: Indiana University Press, 1996), 5. 
[26] Araneta,112.                                                       
[27]  Ibid., 115.
[28] Levinas,  Ethics and Infinity: Conversation with Philippe Nemo, 89.
[29] Levinas, “Transcendence and Height,” 17. (Height explains the other’s appearance and order as if he were a master while humility explains the element of poverty present in the face. In its exposure the face is without defense in any acts of violence).
[30] Araneta, 112-118.
[31] Capili, 2. 
[32] Levinas,  Ethics and Infinity: Conversation with Philippe Nemo, 95.
[33]Levinas,  Ethics and Infinity: Conversation with Philippe Nemo, 96.
[34] Burggraeve, Roger. The Wisdom of Love in the Service of Love: Emmanuel Levinas on Justice, Peace and Human Rights, trans. by Jeffrey Bloechl. (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. 2002), 100.   

[35] Levinas,  Ethics and Infinity: Conversation with Philippe Nemo, 97.
[36] Burggraeve, 102.
[37] Burggraeve, 102.  
[38] Ibid.,  126-127.
[39] Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Easy on Exteriority, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pennsylvania, Duquesne University Press, 1969), 213.
[40] Burggraeve, 127. 
[41] Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Easy on Exteriority, 213.
[42] Peperzak, 127.
[43] Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Easy on Exteriority, 213-214. 

[44] Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Easy on Exteriority,  213.
[45] Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Easy on Exteriority, 214.
[46] Peperzak, 127. 

No comments:

Post a Comment